When liberals go to extremes they typically become either too expedient and pragmatic – sacrificing means to ends – or they become egalitarian heroes, knights in armor slaying dragons of power and privilege. The pragmatism is adopted from a certain strain of conservatism (consider Aristotle celebrating prudence as the highest political virtue and Burke objecting to policy based upon mere rational principle). But the heart and soul of the liberal project has always been egalitarianism, the freeing of individuals from inequitable distributions of power. At first it was fighting for religious dissenters against established churches; then the common man against aristocratic privilege; the individual against the state; the slave against the slave-master; the worker against the capitalist; blacks and other racial minorities against white supremacy; women against patriarchy; gays against homophobia. In each case, liberals have been on the side of the down-trodden against entrenched interest. And that’s how they always see themselves, even when they’re the ones wielding power. But put expediency and egalitarian righteousness together and you have a very potent – and potentially very dangerous – combination.
And that combination
is the driving force behind the new rules and laws addressing sexual assault on
college campuses. No reasonable
person
denies such assault is a very real,
widespread
and terrible problem. According to the Centers for
Disease Control, 19% of undergraduate women have “experienced attempted or
completed sexual assault since entering college.” But19% cannot possibly be the work of a few
deliberate criminals. There must be
something profoundly wrong with the sexual culture itself. Clearly, it happens much too often that the
woman feels coerced and the man either doesn’t realize or doesn’t care. The latter case is clearly rape. The former is not what we would normally call
rape, and at least some of the time it represents little more than male inexperience
and cluelessness. But much of the time it
represents something much darker, something deeply dysfunctional and
destructive: egregious male narcissism and privilege. This is male sexual power maintained through
sheer physical strength, and it engenders female fear and diminishes
female options. It’s hard not to see
all of this as part of the broader social problem of male domination of women.
The new rules
and laws are designed to combat that privilege and domination, and they mostly
do so by implementing “affirmative
consent”, which defines sexual consent as ongoing, explicit agreement, not
the mere absence of explicit refusal. “Yes
means yes” supersedes “No means no.” The state of California recently enacted a law
mandating that all its colleges enforce sexual assault guidelines using the
new, stricter definition of consent. And
many
colleges across the country have instituted new procedures based upon the yes-means-yes
standard.
But many
conservatives
(who generally oppose feminist-inspired change) and
libertarians
(who generally oppose government intervention) find them objectionable, as do
many liberals,
some of whom have characterized the new policies as “illiberal.”
Twenty-eight members
of the Harvard Law faculty recently protested against the procedures Harvard
uses, complaining they “lack the most basic elements of fairness and due
process [and] are overwhelmingly stacked against the accused.” Feminist lawyer
Robin Steinberg worries – as reported by Judith
Shulevitz in a piece titled “Accused College Rapists Have Rights, Too” –
that these new types of rules “reveal a cavalier disregard for the
civil rights of people accused of rape, assault, and other gender-based
crimes.”
Some
supporters of the new rules deny they endanger anyone’s legal or procedural
rights. Ezra
Klein, editor-in-chief of the liberal website vox.com,
writes “there’s no contradiction between a fair and clear process, real
protections for the accused, and an affirmative consent standard — and there's
no reason one shouldn't support all of them simultaneously, as I do.” In theory, of course, that’s true; changing
the standard of sexual consent doesn’t necessarily infringe anyone’s
rights. But trying to legislate such a
strict standard for an activity so inherently full of subtleties
and ambiguities is asking for trouble.
And, unlike the rules for actual criminal courts, where guilt must be
proven beyond a reasonable doubt, a college panel can find a student guilty – and
expel him and ruin his life – based upon only the preponderance of
evidence. The combination of a very high
standard for consent plus a very low one for guilt moves the onus of proof from
the accuser to the accused; it amounts in practice to the elimination
of the presumption of innocence. California’s new law
mandates that even sex within a healthy relationship requires “affirmative
consent” every time, in effect re-labeling almost all present-day sex as
assault. But the law’s defenders say not
to worry, since it will only
be enforced when a woman has been genuinely coerced and not in those countless
everyday cases in which it legally applies.
Well, how reassuring!
But some
defenders of the new law argue that such excess is necessary to effectively
address the problem. Klein is eager to
put the fear of God into all men:
If the Yes Means Yes law is taken even remotely seriously it will
settle like a cold winter on college campuses, throwing everyday sexual
practice into doubt and creating a haze of fear and confusion over what counts
as consent. This is the case against it, and also the case for it. Because for
one in five women to report an attempted or completed sexual assault means that
everyday sexual practices on college campuses need to be upended, and men need
to feel a cold spike of fear when they begin a sexual encounter.
Klein is right
that something must be done to address our dysfunctional, patriarchal sexual
culture, but is suffocating all sexual relations with fear of juridical
authority a constructive way to do so?
Even our rather damning analysis of that undeniable dysfunction concedes
that ambiguous situations can arise innocently.
But Klein’s perfectly OK with criminalizing that ambiguity:
Critics worry that colleges will fill with cases in which campus
boards convict young men (and, occasionally, young women) of sexual assault for
genuinely ambiguous situations. Sadly, that's necessary for the law's success.
It's those cases — particularly the ones that feel genuinely unclear and maybe
even unfair, the ones that become lore in frats and cautionary tales that
fathers e-mail to their sons — that will convince men that they better Be Pretty
Damn Sure.
It is indeed
“sad” that legislating such a strict, unprecedented, unfamiliar, confusing, dangerously
broad standard could harm what are essentially innocent young men, but “it’s
necessary for the law’s success.”
This is the grim
face of authoritarian expediency, all the more alarming for its heedlessness. According to Klein, et al, all women are justifiably
afraid of all men, and that situation must be replaced by one in which all men
are afraid of legal or semi-legal punishment, even unjustified punishment. The
pro-affirmative-consent crowd may dispute it, but their
position in effect is that our normal understandings of due process, presumption
of innocence, and sexual ambiguity stand in the way of protecting women from
the most violent and reprehensible expressions of patriarchy, and therefore
must be discarded. According to Amanda
Taub, female fear of men “reinforces power imbalances that keep women out
of positions of success and authority.”
And here’s Klein with the answer: “Ugly problems don't always have
pretty solutions.” Egalitarian
righteousness plus thoughtless pragmatism equals liberals doing quite illiberal
things.
But the point,
of course, is that it’s not
illiberal, not when you remember that the animating purpose of liberalism is
the fight for the oppressed against the powerful. To affirmative consent supporters, women are
the oppressed and men are the powerful and anything is justified in the service
of female liberation. How can weakening
the rights of oppressors itself be an act of oppression? Habitual identification with the oppressed
seems to prevent liberals from realizing that they’re actually winning the
culture wars, or that they have achieved genuine social and legal
power. In this view, the state and the
university are not capable of oppression, since they fight for the oppressed
against the oppressors. How can agents
of liberation themselves be oppressors? We
see the same dynamic play out in liberal intolerance toward
opponents of same-sex marriage. And
we should note, as does Andrew
Sullivan, the heavy influence on campus culture of post-modernism, with its
insistence that there is no truth independent of some political agenda, and
that, as Michel
Foucault put it, “politics is war by other means”; such views do not
exactly make one conciliatory toward any oppressive class. And we see why the affirmative consent
doctrine has so far only been applied to academia: it’s the only place where
illiberal liberals are powerful enough to get away with it. For
now.
But if
self-righteous identification with the down-trodden is so inherent in
liberalism then why don’t all liberals support the affirmative consent
movement? What is it that makes some
liberals resist? There are two countervailing
principals at play. The first is a broader pragmatism, understood not as mere
expediency, but as something more like humility, as appreciation for the limits
of human action in the face of the unimaginable complexity and intransigence of
human existence. This amounts to a more
tragic view of life, one in which there are no perfect solutions, no set of
principles that would solve all our problems if only we applied them more
thoroughly. The more liberal liberal
understands that some of our most important and desirable goals – such as
liberating women from patriarchy – can conflict with others equally or more
important – such as protecting individuals from authoritarian abuse. And secondly, the wise liberal understands
how particularly important it is to fight that authoritarianism, even the liberal
version. With power comes responsibility
and that responsibility does not disappear simply because your goals are noble
and your cause is just. Virtuous
intentions are meager protection against an overzealous or unscrupulous
prosecutor armed with an ill-conceived and over-reaching law.
The broader,
wiser pragmatism is – like the expediency itself – a borrowing from
conservatism. But the skepticism of
juridical authority is essential to
liberal thought and liberal political culture.
Go back and look at that list of historical liberal fights for the
oppressed. One of the very first is the
protection of the individual against misuse by the state, which primarily takes
the form of individual legal, political and civil rights. Those rights are typically seen as inherent and
inalienable, but we can understand them better as protectors of individual
interest. Libertarians typically treat
them as absolutes and fail to see their instrumental nature. And libertarians fail to perceive any
oppression beyond state oppression.
Modern liberals understand how limited that view is. They’re wise enough to see the iniquitous power
relations that surround us: in capitalism, in culture, in patriarchy, in
religion, in the family. But they must insistently remember the special case of
oppression that is legal oppression, the special danger of a state or a
university with the power to punish and destroy. This is how we keep liberalism honest and
beneficent. Wisdom demands that we respect the destructive power of all those
oppressions, while humility demands we acknowledge the limits of
liberation. But crucially, the earnest, passionate
liberal hatred of oppression demands we never sacrifice the most important
liberation for any other.
No comments:
Post a Comment